Catholic Candle note: The article immediately below is part seven of the study of the Choleric temperament. The first fix parts can be found here:
1. Mary’s School of Sanctity – Lesson #36: About the Temperaments – Beginning our Study of the Choleric Temperament: https://catholiccandle.org/2024/08/27/lesson-35-about-the-temperaments-the-choleric-temperament/
2. Mary’s School of Sanctity – Lesson #37: About the Temperaments – Continuing Our Study of the Choleric Temperament: https://catholiccandle.org/2024/09/26/lesson-37-about-the-temperaments-continuation-of-the-choleric-temperament/
3. Mary’s School of Sanctity – Lesson #38 — About the Temperaments – Continuing our Study of the Choleric Temperament – Their Spiritual Combat: https://catholiccandle.org/2024/10/24/lesson-38-temperaments-choleric-temperament-their-spiritual-combat/
4. Mary’s School of Sanctity – Lesson #39 About the Temperaments – Continuing Our Study of the Choleric Temperament – That Temperament’s Spiritual Combat – Part IV: https://catholiccandle.org/2024/11/26/lesson-39-temperaments-choleric-temperament-their-spiritual-combat-part-iv/
5. Mary’s School of Sanctity – Lesson #40: Temperaments – Choleric Temperament – Their Spiritual Combat – Part V: https://catholiccandle.org/2024/12/30/lesson-40-temperaments-choleric-temperament-their-spiritual-combat-part-v/
6. Mary’s School of Sanctity – Lesson #41 – About the Temperaments – Continuing Our Study of the Choleric Temperament: a Choleric’s Spiritual Combat — Part VI: https://catholiccandle.org/2025/01/27/lesson-41-temperaments-choleric-temperament-a-cholerics-spiritual-combat-part-vi/
Mary’s School of Sanctity
Lesson #42: About the Temperaments – Continuing Our Study of the Choleric Temperament – a Choleric’s Spiritual Combat – Part VII
Note: When referring to a person with a choleric temperament in this article we simply will label him as a choleric.
In our last two lessons we have described: how one is moved to anger; what effects anger has on the body; and how anger affects the proper use of one’s reason.
Also, we saw in Lesson #41, in particular, how anger requires an act of reason insofar as one seeks just vengeance when he has been wronged. Furthermore, we saw that because anger causes changes in the body, these changes hamper the proper role of one’s reason.
Since anger is a passion and classified as one of the seven capital sins, we need to be careful in our understanding of anger. Let us consider the following three points:
1) When is anger lawful?
2) When is anger sinful?
3) When anger is sinful, how does it connect with additional sins, such as, hatred?
1) When is anger lawful?
St. Thomas clarifies the answer to this question for us in the following explanation:
Now this [the evil of envy][1] does not apply to anger, which is the desire for revenge, since revenge may be desired both well and ill. Secondly, evil is found in a passion in respect to the passion’s quantity, that is, in respect to its excess or deficiency; and thus, evil may be found in anger, when, to wit, one is angry, more or less than right reason demands. But if one is angry in accordance with right reason, one’s anger is deserving of praise.[2]
St. Thomas explains in more depth when he comments on St. Gregory’s work On Morals:
Anger may stand in a twofold relation to reason. First, antecedently; in this way it withdraws reason from its rectitude, and has therefore the character of evil. Secondly, consequently, inasmuch as the movement of the sensitive appetite is directed against vice and in accordance with reason, this anger is good, and is called zealous anger. Wherefore, Gregory says (De Moral. vol. 45): “We must beware lest, when we use anger as an instrument of virtue, it overrules the mind, and go before it as its mistress, instead of following in reason’s train, ever ready, as its handmaid, to obey.” This latter anger, although it hinders somewhat the judgment of reason in the execution of the act, does not destroy the rectitude of reason. Hence Gregory says (Moral. v, 45) that zealous anger troubles the eye of reason, whereas sinful anger blinds it. Nor is it incompatible with virtue that the deliberation of reason be interrupted in the execution of what reason has deliberated: since art also would be hindered in its act, if it were to deliberate about what has to be done, while having to act.[3]
2) When does anger become sinful?
St. Thomas gives us guidelines here as well:
Anger, as stated above (a.1), is properly the name of a passion. A passion of the sensitive appetite is good in so far as it is regulated by reason, whereas it is evil if it set the order of reason aside. Now the order of reason, in regard to anger, may be considered in relation to two things. First, in relation to the appetible [desirable] object to which anger tends, and that is revenge. Wherefore if one desire revenge to be taken in accordance with the order of reason, the desire of anger is praiseworthy, and is called zealous anger [*Cf. Greg., Moral. v, 45]. On the other hand, if one desire the taking of vengeance in any way whatever contrary to the order of reason, for instance if he desire the punishment of one who has not deserved it, or beyond his deserts, or again contrary to the order prescribed by law, or not for the due end, namely the maintaining of justice and the correction of faults, then the desire of anger will be sinful, and this is called sinful anger.
Secondly, the order of reason in regard to anger may be considered in relation to the mode of being angry, namely that the movement of anger should not be immoderately fierce, neither internally nor externally; and if this condition be disregarded [namely, the proper degree of anger], anger will not lack sin, even though just vengeance be desired.[4]
3) When anger is sinful, how does it connect with additional sins, such as, hatred?
St. Thomas makes some very interesting and useful distinctions regarding the forms of anger when defending the names and descriptions that Aristotle used. He cites the authority of St. Gregory of Nyssa, a father of the Church.
St. Gregory of Nyssa says there are three species of irascibility, namely, the anger which is called wrath, and ill-will which is a disease of the mind, and rancor. Now these three seem to coincide with the three aforesaid [viz., the three-fold division used by Aristotle]. For wrath he describes as having beginning and movement, and the Philosopher (Ethic. iv, 5) ascribes this to choleric persons: ill-will he describes as an anger that endures and grows old and this the Philosopher ascribes to sullenness; while he describes rancor as reckoning the time for vengeance, which tallies with the Philosopher’s description of the ill-tempered. The same division is given by Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 16). Therefore, the aforesaid division assigned by the Philosopher is not unfitting.[5]
St. Thomas continues his explanation as follows here:
The aforesaid distinction may be referred either to the passion, or to the sin itself of anger. We have already stated when treating of the passions (I-II, Q. 46, A. 8) how it is to be applied to the passion of anger. And it would seem that this is chiefly what Gregory of Nyssa and Damascene had in view. Here, however, we have to take the distinction of these species in its application to the sin of anger, and as set down by the Philosopher. For the inordinateness of anger may be considered in relation to two things. First, in relation to the origin of anger, and this regards choleric persons, who are angry too quickly and for any slight cause. Secondly, in relation to the duration of anger, for that anger endures too long; and this may happen in two ways. In one way, because the cause of anger, to wit, the inflicted injury, remains too long in a man’s memory, the result being that it gives rise to a lasting displeasure, wherefore he is grievous and sullen to himself. In another way, it happens on the part of vengeance, which a man seeks with a stubborn desire: this applies to ill-tempered or stern people, who do not put aside their anger until they have inflicted punishment.[6]
Then St. Thomas gives us additional information about the dangers that come with sullenness and being ill-tempered.
Both sullen and ill-tempered people have a long-lasting anger, but for different reasons. For a sullen person has an abiding anger on account of an abiding displeasure, which he holds locked in his breast; and as he does not break forth into the outward signs of anger, others cannot reason him out of it, nor does he of his own accord lay aside his anger, unless his displeasure wear away with time and thus his anger cease. On the other hand, the anger of ill-tempered persons is long-lasting on account of their intense desire for revenge, so that it does not wear out with time, and can be quelled only by revenge.[7]
An additional important aspect about anger is to see the connection between what St. Thomas has explained about holding anger inside and the situation in which the angry person becomes taciturn. Let’s see St. Thomas’s explanation here:
On the part of the impediment to reason because, as stated above (A. 2), the disturbance of anger reaches to the outward members, and chiefly to those members which reflect more distinctly the emotions of the heart, such as the eyes, face and tongue; wherefore, as observed above (A. 2), the tongue stammers, the countenance takes fire, the eyes grow fierce. Consequently, anger may cause such a disturbance, that the tongue is altogether deprived of speech; and taciturnity is the result. [8]
St. Thomas quotes St. Gregory when referring to this taciturnity, “Gregory says (De Moral. v, 30) that when anger does not vent itself outwardly by the lips, inwardly it burns the more fiercely.”[9]
Now we can see how long-lasting and deep-seated anger has additional serious consequences. For St. Thomas tells us that when anger lasts a long time, it engenders hatred. Here are his words:
Anger is said to grow into hatred, not as though the same passion which at first was anger, afterwards becomes hatred by becoming inveterate; but by a process of causality. For anger when it lasts a long time engenders hatred.[10]
Since St. Thomas teaches us that anger can turn into hatred, it would be an appropriate time to see what he teaches us about the seriousness of hatred.
St. Thomas investigates whether anger is graver than hatred. He concludes that hatred is graver than anger. He explains his conclusion as follows:
The species and nature of a passion are taken from its object. However, the object of anger is the same in substance as the object of hatred; since, just as the hater wishes evil to him whom he hates, so does the angry man wish evil to him with whom he is angry. But there is a difference of aspect: for the hater wishes evil to his enemy, as evil, whereas the angry man wishes evil to him with whom he is angry, not as evil but in so far as it has an aspect of good, that is, in so far as he reckons it as just, since it is a means of vengeance. Wherefore also it has been said above (A. 2) that hatred implies application of evil to evil, whereas anger denotes application of good to evil. However, it is evident that to seek evil under the aspect of justice, is a lesser evil, than simply to seek evil to someone. Because to wish evil to someone under the aspect of justice, may be according to the virtue of justice, if it be in conformity with the order of reason; and anger fails only in this, that it does not obey the precept of reason in taking vengeance. Consequently, it is evident that hatred is far worse and graver than anger.[11]
We add an additional explanation that St. Thomas gives regarding the differences between anger and hatred.
In anger and hatred two points may be considered: namely, the thing desired, and the intensity of the desire. As to the thing desired, anger has more mercy than hatred has. For since hatred desires another’s evil for evil’s sake, it is satisfied with no particular measure of evil: because those things that are desired for their own sake, are desired without measure, as the Philosopher states (Politic Bk. 1; ch.9 #1257b26)[12], instancing a miser with regard to riches. Hence it is written (Ecclus. 12:16): “An enemy . . . if he find an opportunity, will not be satisfied with blood.” Anger, on the other hand, seeks evil only under the aspect of a just means of vengeance. Consequently, when the evil inflicted goes beyond the measure of justice according to the estimate of the angry man, then he has mercy. Wherefore, the Philosopher says (Rhetoric Bk.2; ch.4 #1382a8) that the angry man is appeased if many evils befall, whereas the hater is never appeased.[13] As to the intensity of the desire, anger excludes mercy more than hatred does; because the movement of anger is more impetuous, through the heating of the bile. Hence the passage quoted continues: “Who can bear the violence of one provoked?”[14]
We can see plainly from what St. Thomas has set forth and the striking quote from Aristotle’s Rhetoric (in the footnote before last), that sinful anger must be shunned with all one’s might. Not only does unreasonable anger lead to further sin, but it also is closely joined with pride.
A Preview…
We will look more into the connection of how pride fosters anger and other sins. In our next lesson we will look into ways that a choleric can learn how to keep himself in check. We will also look at ways in which he can curb his anger and refrain from holding grudges – which have direct links to hatred as we have shown above.
[1] Here, St. Thomas is commenting on a quote from Aristotle: “The very mention of envy denotes something evil.” These words are found here: Ethics, Bk.2, ch.6.
[2] Summa Theologica, IIa IIae, Q.158, a.1, Respondeo.
[3] Summa Theologica, IIa IIae, Q.158, a.1, ad. 2.
[4] Summa Theologica, IIa IIae, Q.158, a.2 Respondeo, [bracketed words are added for clarification].
[5] Summa Theologica, IIa IIae, Q.158, a.5, Sed Contra (bracketed words added for clarity). The citation of St. Gregory of Nyssa is from Nemesius, De Nat. Hom. Xxi and the word ‘wrath’ in the citation above is rendered from the word ‘Fellea’, i.e., like gall. But in Ia IIae, Q.46, a.8, St. Thomas quoting the same authority has ‘Cholos’ which the translators of St. Thomas rendered to be the word ‘wrath’.
[6] Summa Theologica, IIa IIae, Q.158, a.5, Respondeo.
[7] Summa Theologica, IIa IIae, Q.158 a.6 ad.2.
[8] Summa Theologica, Ia Iiae, Q.48 a.4, Respondeo.
[9] Summa Theologica, Ia Iiae, Q.48 a.4, Sed Contra.
[10] Summa Theologica, Ia Iiae, Q.46 a.3, ad.2.
[11] Summa Theologica, Ia IIae, Q. 46, a.6, Respondeo, [bold emphasis added].
[12] Here are the words of Aristotle to which St. Thomas refers:
As in the art of medicine there is no limit to the pursuit of health, and as in the other arts there is no limit to the pursuit of their several ends, for they aim at accomplishing their ends to the uttermost (but of the means there is a limit, for the end is always the limit), so, too, in this art of wealth-getting there is no limit of the end, which is riches of the spurious kind, and the acquisition of wealth.
Aristotle’s Politics, Bk. 1; ch.3, #1257b26”.
[13] The quote that St. Thomas refers to is from Aristotle and is quite striking:
Moreover, anger can be cured by time, but hatred cannot.
Here are Aristotle’s fuller explanation from this same passage, to give a fuller context:
The one aims at giving pain to its object, the other at doing him harm; the angry man wants his victims to feel; the hater does not care whether they feel or not. All painful things are felt; but the greatest evils, injustice and folly, are the least felt, since their presence causes no pain. And anger is accompanied by pain, hatred is not; the angry man feels pain, but the hater does not. Much may happen to make the angry man pity those who offend him, but the hater under no circumstances wishes to pity a man whom he has once hated: for the one would have the offenders suffer for what they have done; the other would have them cease to exist.
Aristotle’s Rhetoric Bk.2; ch.4 #1382a8. Bold emphasis added to highlight the gravity of the sin of hatred.
[14] Summa Theologica, Ia IIae, Q.46, a.6, ad.1.